This morning there was a "quote of the day" on my iGoogle page that I take issue with:
"Faith is a cop-out. It is intellectual bankruptcy. If the only way you can accept an assertion is by faith, then you are conceding that it can’t be taken on its own merits" (Dan Barker).
How do you know that this is true?
By reason?
How do you know that reason is a valid foundation for truth?
By reason?
Right.
Faith is an absolutely necessary part of any philosophical position. I discussed this in my previous post. Ironically, it appears as though this quotation is from a book entitled Losing Faith in Faith. I think Mr. Barker should question the amount of faith he has placed in reason.
Saturday, September 6, 2008
Monday, July 14, 2008
The heart of philosophy
Christianity is often condemned for its circular reasoning, and postmodernism is often condemned for its contradictions. However, we cannot reasonably expect the heart of any philosophy (including Christianity) to be free of both circular reasoning and contradiction. One or both of these are of necessity at the heart of every philosophy.
Circular reasoning or contradiction are the necessary result of supporting our philosophy, or more specifically, our epistemology, on the most basic level. The problematic question is simply, "How do we know that this is how we know?" We have only two ways to answer: we must either step outside or stay within our philosophy. If we step outside the philosophy to answer this question, we contradict ourselves. For example, if we attempt to show that postmodernism must be reasonably believed, we are, to oversimplify, saying, "How do we know that reason is an invalid basis for truth? By reason." If we use reason to demonstrate that Christ or the Bible should be the foundation for truth, we reach the same contradiction.
The other option is to stay within the philosophy to answer the question. This leads to circular reasoning. Christians are guilty of this when they say something like, "How do we know that God exists? By the Bible. How do we know the Bible is true? Because it came from God."
We cannot satistfactorily support any philosophy on the most basic level. We must therefore seek to find, not conclusive proof, but good grounds for believing in a philosophy.
Circular reasoning or contradiction are the necessary result of supporting our philosophy, or more specifically, our epistemology, on the most basic level. The problematic question is simply, "How do we know that this is how we know?" We have only two ways to answer: we must either step outside or stay within our philosophy. If we step outside the philosophy to answer this question, we contradict ourselves. For example, if we attempt to show that postmodernism must be reasonably believed, we are, to oversimplify, saying, "How do we know that reason is an invalid basis for truth? By reason." If we use reason to demonstrate that Christ or the Bible should be the foundation for truth, we reach the same contradiction.
The other option is to stay within the philosophy to answer the question. This leads to circular reasoning. Christians are guilty of this when they say something like, "How do we know that God exists? By the Bible. How do we know the Bible is true? Because it came from God."
We cannot satistfactorily support any philosophy on the most basic level. We must therefore seek to find, not conclusive proof, but good grounds for believing in a philosophy.
Wednesday, July 9, 2008
"Ten Days in a Mad-House"
Today I read a fascinating book, Ten Days in a Mad-House, by Nellie Bly. Nellie was a newspaper reporter around the turn of the century who investigated the conditions of insane asylums by having herself committed to one. In this short book she details her horrifying experience . It's no longer in print, but you can read it here. Very interesting!
Letter from Senator Schumer
On Monday I emailed our senators, Charles Schumer and Hillary Clinton, to ask them to oppose the FISA bill. I was surprised and pleased to receive this email in response from Senator Schumer:
Thank you for your e-mail. Each and every piece of correspondence I receive is important because it allows me to better understand the New Yorkers I serve in the United States Senate.While I don't agree with much of what Senator Schumer stands for, this email caused me to gain some respect for him. I appreciated this acknowledgement - even in an automatically generated email - that he is listening.
As you can imagine, my office receives a great number of messages every day regarding a variety of issues – this is particularly true of e-mails. It makes me proud to know that my constituents take an active role in our government by corresponding with me, and I look forward to responding to your concerns in greater detail. In the meantime, I just wanted to let you know that your e-mail has been received, and to ask for your patience until I send you a more detailed response.
Again, thank you for writing. Please feel free to visit my website http://schumer.senate.gov to follow my work in the Senate and to learn more about the services my office can provide to you.
Warmest regards
Friday, July 4, 2008
Privacy vs. National Security
I just got back from a week at moot court camp at PHC. The camp was extremely intense, perhaps overly so, but moot court itself was a lot of fun. The topic was "National Security vs. Privacy." The problem (you can read it here; note, however, that William Denolf did not appear in the problem we worked with) was extremely complicated and there were no easy answers, but ultimately I came down on the Libertarian side of the issue (surprise!). In brief, the government needed a warrant to surveil Bronner and Comerford.
Here's why (a summary of my petitioner case):
This was never discussed in a moot court round, but there is a critical flaw in this argument, and that is that email is not first class mail. The argument implies that if first class mail may be searched at the border, then surely email - a less private form of communication - may be searched also. But the difference between first class mail and email is that with first class mail, something physical crosses the border, whereas with email, electrons cross the border. The purpose of border searches of first class mail is to prevent the introduction of illegal substances into the country; simply glancing at the context of Montoya definitively settles this. The reasoning for warrantless searches of first class mail may not be applied to email.
The issue at stake here is not surveillance, but warrantless surveillance. We should certainly uphold the president's power to preserve national security, but we must insist that he follow the proper channels when doing so.
Here's why (a summary of my petitioner case):
ReasoningOn the respondent side, one of the best arguments we had was the international nature of the communication. Regardless of one's beliefs as to the international elements of the case, it remains an undisputed fact that the petitioners' communication was international in nature. And the government has the power to surveil international communication. In U.S. v. Montoya de Herdandez, the Supreme Court noted that at the border, even first class mail may be searched without a warrant. The Court wrote that "the Fourth Amendment's balance of reasonableness is qualitatively different at the international border than in the interior. Routine searches of the persons and effects of entrants are not subject to any requirement of reasonable suspicion, probable cause, or warrant, and first-class mail may be opened without a warrant on less than probable cause." Since the petitioners were communicating through foreign email accounts and foreign servers, the government certainly had the power to search.
In the 1967 case Katz v. United States, the Supreme Court ruled that an individual is not subject to warrantless search if he has a reasonable expectation of privacy. As we look over the facts of this case, we will see that 1) the petitioners had a reasonable expectation of privacy, 2) the government did not meet the warrant requirement, and 3) the result of these two facts is that the search was unreasonable and therefore unconstitutional.
Bronner and Comerford had a reasonable expectation of privacy. In Katz, the Supreme Court ruled that this must be twofold: it must be subjective, and it must be objective. A subjective expectation of privacy answers the question, "Did the individuals believe that their communication was private?" That Bronner and Comerford did was directly stated in the problem. In Katz the Court ruled that "what an individual seeks to preserve as private, even in an area accessible to the public, may be constitutionally protected." Our problem states that BATM, of which the petitioners were members, "took measures aimed at making additional government surveillance difficult if not unlikely." Obviously, they sought to preserve their communication as private and therefore had a subjective expectation of privacy.
An objective expectation of privacy asks the question, "Was the individuals' expecation of privacy one that society is willing to accept?" The answer to this is a resounding "yes." These were private emails that the government was surveilling. The petitioners were "surely entitled to assume that their communication would not be broadcast to the world" [Katz]. To read the Constitution more narrowly, is, according to Katz, to "ignore the role that public telephone [in this case, wireless internet] has come to play in private communication."
As a result of the petitioners' reasonable expectation of privacy, the government needed a warrant to surveil. In U.S. v U.S. District Court and Katz, the Supreme Court ruled that there are two requirements for a warrant: it must be granted prior to search, and it must be granted by a neutral magistrate. Neither of these requirements were met. The government stumbled upon the information and continued to search without even attempting to apply for any warrant of any kind at any point throughout the case. Obviously, no neutral magistrate was ever involved. None whatsoever.
As a result of Bronner and Comerford's reasonable expectation of privacy and the government's failure to meet the warrant requirement, the search was, in the language of Katz, "per se unreasonable" and therefore, unconstitutional.
This was never discussed in a moot court round, but there is a critical flaw in this argument, and that is that email is not first class mail. The argument implies that if first class mail may be searched at the border, then surely email - a less private form of communication - may be searched also. But the difference between first class mail and email is that with first class mail, something physical crosses the border, whereas with email, electrons cross the border. The purpose of border searches of first class mail is to prevent the introduction of illegal substances into the country; simply glancing at the context of Montoya definitively settles this. The reasoning for warrantless searches of first class mail may not be applied to email.
The issue at stake here is not surveillance, but warrantless surveillance. We should certainly uphold the president's power to preserve national security, but we must insist that he follow the proper channels when doing so.
Wednesday, April 23, 2008
"Jam," by Karen Chase
I usually hate stream-of-consciousness writing. It confuses and irritates me. (See "Susie Asado," by Gertrude Stein.) However, the poem "Jam," by Karen Chase, is a definite exception. The stream-of-consciousness style fits the subject matter of "Jam" perfectly. The end result is unique, interesting, and very enjoyable. You can read "Jam" here.
Saturday, April 12, 2008
π
I wrote a calculator program a couple days ago to calculate pi. It was a very interesting experiment!
I used a Taylor series to do this. If you let f(x) = arctan(x), then if x = 1, f(x) = π/4. So if you calculate the Taylor series for f(x), the sum as the number of terms approaches infinity will approach π/4. Here's the series:
∞
y = Σ (-1)^(n-1) * x^(2n-1) / (2n-1)
n=1
Let x=1, and then multiply the series by 4.
I programmed my brother's TI-84 Plus SE (because that's much faster than my TI-83) to calculate about 10,000 terms of the series. The calculator thought for about two minutes, and returned an answer that was only correct to four or five digits. That gave me a new respect for supercomputers that can calculate billions of digits of pi! I wish I knew of a way to plug this equation into our computer and see how it did.
I used a Taylor series to do this. If you let f(x) = arctan(x), then if x = 1, f(x) = π/4. So if you calculate the Taylor series for f(x), the sum as the number of terms approaches infinity will approach π/4. Here's the series:
∞
y = Σ (-1)^(n-1) * x^(2n-1) / (2n-1)
n=1
Let x=1, and then multiply the series by 4.
I programmed my brother's TI-84 Plus SE (because that's much faster than my TI-83) to calculate about 10,000 terms of the series. The calculator thought for about two minutes, and returned an answer that was only correct to four or five digits. That gave me a new respect for supercomputers that can calculate billions of digits of pi! I wish I knew of a way to plug this equation into our computer and see how it did.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)